Passions (philosophy)

In philosophy and religion, the passions are understood to be the emotions, instincts and desires that drive a human being (including lust, anger, aggression, jealousy, etc.). Different philosophical traditions hold different views about the passions. The philosophical notion of passion, in contrast, is generally identified with instinctually driven emotional states regarded, in many ancient philosophies and religious doctrines, as being the basis for deadly sins and seen as leading to various social and spiritual ills. In Western philosophical traditions, the passions are often placed in opposition to reason.[1][2]

Some seventeenth-century philosophers worked within an intellectual milieu in which passions were regarded as a potent element of human nature, capable of disrupting any civilized order, including philosophy, unless they were tamed, outwitted, overruled, or seduced.[3] Natural philosophy deals with the actions and operations of passions, and the task of moral philosophy is to explore whether and how the passions can, or should be bridled, and how their indifference is transformed into good or evil by virtue of the domination of right reason.[4] Reason is advocated in the control of passion, something seen as desirable and necessary for the development of a mature, civilized human being. This is achieved by the cultivation of virtue. Four virtues in particular have long been seen as of special value in this regard.

The majority of philosophies and religions advocate at the very least tempering the passions to keep them within acceptable bounds. However, most of the great religions recommend both the restraint and the transformation of the passions to the point where they no longer arise. This is true of Christianity, Jainism, Buddhism, Islam and Hinduism. The institution of the monastery within various religions is a means by which human beings may temporarily or permanently seclude themselves from circumstances exacerbating the arising of passion and provide a supportive environment for doing spiritual work.

Contemporary philosopher Roberto Mangabeira Unger has developed a view of the passions that disassociates them from human nature, and instead gives them a formless life that serve iur non-instrumental dealings with each other. Rather than the guiding force behind our relations with the world, they organize and are organized around the need and danger that is at the heart of our relations with each other. In this way, Unger rejects the traditional view of the passions as something counter to reason and which are associated with certain expressions; rather, he sees them at the service of reason and their expression formed within certain contexts.[5]

  1. ^ Taliaferro, Charles (2023), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), "Philosophy of Religion", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2023 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-04-10
  2. ^ "Faith and Reason | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2024-04-10.
  3. ^ "Stoicism - Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy". www.rep.routledge.com. Retrieved 2024-04-10.
  4. ^ James, Susan (16 October 1997). Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-151912-3.
  5. ^ Unger, Roberto Mangabeira (1986). Passion: An Essay on Personality. New York: Free Press. ISBN 0-02-933180-3.

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia · View on Wikipedia

Developed by Nelliwinne